tar.weatherson.orgThoughts Arguments and Rants

tar.weatherson.org Profile

Tar.weatherson.org is a subdomain of weatherson.org, which was created on 2006-06-20,making it 18 years ago.

Description:Thoughts Arguments and...

Discover tar.weatherson.org website stats, rating, details and status online.Use our online tools to find owner and admin contact info. Find out where is server located.Read and write reviews or vote to improve it ranking. Check alliedvsaxis duplicates with related css, domain relations, most used words, social networks references. Go to regular site

tar.weatherson.org Information

HomePage size: 294.425 KB
Page Load Time: 0.733223 Seconds
Website IP Address: 208.76.86.144

tar.weatherson.org Similar Website

Prescription Drug Costs Pros and Cons - 8 Arguments For and Against
prescriptiondrugs.procon.org
William's Personal Web Server and Random Thoughts
greyghost.mooo.com
Multiplex: Deleted Scenes — Bonus comics, movie reviews, and random rants
blog.multiplexcomic.com
RHDJapan Blog - Blog on JDM news, racing, drifting and thoughts from OsakaRHDJapan Blog
blog.rhdjapan.com
Cat's Rants - Confessions of an Occult Mastermind
originalninjacat.typepad.com
Gentle Wisdom - Thoughts on life from Peter KirkGentle Wisdom | Thoughts on life from Peter Kirk
gentlewisdom.italiapa.com
Spartan Ideas | A collection of thoughts, ideas, and opinions independently written by members of t
spartanideas.msu.edu
John Cuppi — tech blog and other thoughts
john.cuppi.net
Conscious Junkyard | thoughts, ramblings, and rants
kenklaser.gaiastream.com
Rants inside
ucla.jamesyxu.com
The Thing That is Steve | The thoughts and quirks of Steve Caruso and the antics of his family.
steve.rogueleaf.com
Rants oh my blog - lauradarbysinghcom
kenya.darbysingh.com
cek.log : Geeky rants from Charlie Kindel...
ceklog.kindel.com

tar.weatherson.org PopUrls

Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/
May | 2009 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2009/05/
March | 2010 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2010/03/
May | 2005 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2005/05/
November | 2004 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
https://tar.weatherson.org/2004/11/
February | 2005 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2005/02/
January | 2006 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2006/01/
August | 2003 | Thoughts Arguments and Rants
https://tar.weatherson.org/2003/08/
December | 2002 - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2002/12/
Brian Weatherson - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/author/brian-weatherson/
The Evil Demon Argument - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2007/10/08/the-evil-demon-argument/
Philosophy in Questionable Taste - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2004/03/10/philosophy-in-questionable-taste/
What is the Equal Weight View of Disagreement?
http://tar.weatherson.org/2010/04/04/what-is-the-equal-weight-view-of-disagreement/
The Philosophy of Flirting - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2006/09/13/the-philosophy-of-flirting/
Testing Realism? - Thoughts Arguments and Rants
http://tar.weatherson.org/2007/04/25/testing-realism/

tar.weatherson.org Httpheader

Date: Tue, 14 May 2024 21:30:27 GMT
Server: Apache
Link: http://tar.weatherson.org/wp-json/; rel="https://api.w.org/"
Upgrade: h2,h2c
Connection: Upgrade
Vary: Accept-Encoding
Transfer-Encoding: chunked
Content-Type: text/html; charset=UTF-8

tar.weatherson.org Meta Info

charset="utf-8"/
content="width=device-width, initial-scale=1" name="viewport"/
content="WordPress 5.2.20" name="generator"
content="tfwp" name="twitter:partner"/
content="summary" name="twitter:card"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" name="twitter:title"/
content="en_US" property="og:locale"
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" property="og:site_name"
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" property="og:title"
content="http://tar.weatherson.org" property="og:url"
content="website" property="og:type"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" property="og:description"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" itemprop="name"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" itemprop="headline"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" itemprop="description"/
itemprop="publisher" content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants"/
content="http://tar.weatherson.org" name="twitter:url"/
content="Thoughts Arguments and Rants" name="twitter:description"/
content="summary_large_image" name="twitter:card"/

tar.weatherson.org Ip Information

Ip Country: United States
Latitude: 37.751
Longitude: -97.822

tar.weatherson.org Html To Plain Text

Scroll down to content Posts Posted on 11 May, 2018 Value and News in Evidential Decision Theory InDesire as Belief, Lewis Notwithstanding , Ruth Weintraub argues that Lewis’s refutation of Desire as Belief rests on an implausible theory of desirability. In particular, she argues that the additivity principle Lewis uses in the proof is implausible. After a bit of algebra, she concludes with this (correct) theorem in the logic of desirability Lewis uses, and an argument against Lewis’s interpretation of it. So if \(D(A) = D(B)\) and \(D(\neg A) = D(\neg B)\), \(A\) and \(B\) have the same probability. But this shows that D isn’t a measure of the goodness of propositions (prospects). For there can be equally good prospects whose probabilities differ. Suppose, for instance, I have two lottery tickets, for two different lotteries. The (single) prize in both lotteries is $1,000, but there are twice as many tickets in the second one. The two prospects (winning in the first lottery and winning in the second) seem equally good, as do the prospects of not winning. But if ‘I win in the first lottery’ has the same desirability as ‘I win in the second lottery’, the desirability of ‘I do not win in the first lottery’ cannot equal that of ‘I do not win in the second lottery’. The more probable outcome, not winning in the second lottery, is less undesirable. If, alternatively, not winning in the lotteries is equally (un)desirable, then winning in the second is more desirable. (Weintraub 2007, 120, notation slightly altered). But this isn’t quite right. Let \(A\) be that I win the first lottery, and \(B\) be that I win the second lottery. Then although the prize for each lottery is the same, \(D(B)D(A)\). That’s because \(B\) means that I win $1,000, and have a ticket in a lottery I have a good chance of winning. But \(A\) means that I win $1,000, and have a ticket in a lottery I have a bad chance of winning. And the first is better for me than the second. Weintraub has a second argument against the additivity principle. Assume \(P(A) = 1\), and \(T\) is a tautology. $$D(T) = \frac{D(A)P(A) + D(\neg A)P(\neg A)}{P(A) + P(\neg A)} = D(A)$$ She comments But this is absurd. When I win the lottery and am certain that I have won, I find my winning as good as I did when it seemed very unlikely. But according to its desirability (that of a tautology), I am indifferent to it! (Weintraub 2007, 120, emphasis in original) This assumes that I am indifferent to tautologies. And on the correct way to understand Jeffrey’s theory, this isn’t quite right. After all, if things are going very very well for me, then \(D(T)\) will be extremely high. In general, the value of \(D(T)\) at a time is a reflection of how well things are going for me at that time. Of course, at any given time it is possible to use \(D(T)\) as a baseline, and say that how good something is is given by the difference between its desirability and \(D(T)\). But we should remember that across time on Jeffrey’s theory, \(D(T)\) can change dramatically. And those changes have meaning; they reflect changes in the value the agent assigns to their current overall state. So there isn’t anything absurd about \(D(T) = D(A)\) after I win the lottery. Both of them are high. ‘Learning’ either of them doesn’t improve things for me. But that doesn’t mean I’m indifferent to them; I’m rather happy that both of them are true. There is something very funny about this view, though it’s not that \(D(T) = D(A)\). Imagine that a good thing, \(A\), and a bad thing \(B\) both happen, and I know they’ve both happened. Then we have \(D(A) = D(B)\), which seems odd. This is why I’d like to have some kind of theory of value like the proposal by Stephen Daskall I discussed in the previous post. Things now, with \(A \wedge B\) true, are as they are. But they’d be worse if \(A\) were false, and better if \(B\) were false. And there should be a way of turning that into a theory of ‘absolute value’. But I don’t see how one could do that consistent with any kind of Desire as Belief theory. Posted on 11 May, 2018 11 May, 2018 Absolute Value In Absolute Value as Belief , Steven Daskal aims to save anti-Humeanism against Lewis’s attacks in the Desire as Belief papers by changing the connection between credences and values. I like the idea he’s trying to develop – trying to use the difference in value between \(A\) and \(\neg A\) to state the theory more carefully. But the particular way he does it isn’t quite working, and I don’t really know how to fix it. Here is the equation he ends up wanting to defend. $$\sum_y C(g(A) = y) \cdot y = \sum_w C(w) \cdot (V(w \bullet A) – V(w \bullet \neg A))$$ The sum on the left is over possible values. The sum on the right is over possible worlds. And the \(\bullet\) is an imaging operator; so \(w \bullet A\) is the nearest world to \(w\) where \(A\) is true. (The general form of this allows ties, but we won’t need that level of specificity.) I don’t think this can be right in general as it stands. Here is a puzzle case for the view. Assume there are three equiprobable worlds, \(w_1, w_2, w_3\), and the first two have goodness 1, the third has goodness 0. Assume also that these goodness facts are known. Let \(A\) be the proposition that \(w_1\) obtains. So we have the following for the LHS of the equation. $$\sum_y C(g(A) = y) \cdot y = C(g(A) = 1) \cdot 1 = 1$$ Assuming that strong centring obtains for the ‘nearness’ function, we get the following. \(w_1 \bullet A = w_1\) \(w_2 \bullet A = w_1\) \(w_2 \bullet \neg A = w_2\) \(w_3 \bullet A = w_1\) \(w_3 \bullet \neg A = w_3\) It isn’t clear what \(w_1 \bullet \neg A\) should be; let’s call it \(w_x\). Substituting all these into the RHS of the equation we get: $$\frac{V(w_1) – V(w_x)}{3} + \frac{V(w_1) – V(w_2)}{3} + \frac{V(w_1) – V(w_3)}{3}$$ The second term equals 0, and the third term equals 1/3. The value of the first term is unknown, but it is either 0 or 1/3. So the sum equals either 1/3 or 2/3. So we have LHS equals 1, and RHS equals either 1/3 or 2/3. So the equation doesn’t work. As I said, I like the idea of using differences between values of propositions and their negations in the theory of motivation. But I don’t think this particular way of doing it is quite right. Posted on 18 May, 2017 Over Time, Citations Get More Uneven In an earlier post, I compared the distribution of citations within Journal of Philosophy , 1976 and Philosophical Studies , 2009. And I noted that although the two ended up in similar places, they got there in different ways. Journal of Philosophy was largely relying on some hugely cited papers; while the distribution of citations in Philosophical Studies was more even. And I suggested that this was part of a trend in the discipline towards more egalitarian citation practices. In Facebook comments on this post, Ben Blumson and Peter Michael Gerdes suggested an alternative explanation. Perhaps the citations are more unbalanced in Journal of Philosophy , 1976 because the longer a journal is out, the more a consensus builds up around what the great papers are in it, and the more those papers (and those papers only) get cited. In effect, I was seeing an age effect, and viewing it as a cohort effect. So I looked at the data, and it looks like they were very largely correct. All the points below come from investigating the citations to papers in Journal of Philosophy , 1976. I broke the citations up into those appearing before and after 1995. In fact more of the citations come after 1995, which was surprising. (That might be due to Web of Science’s coverage getting more comprehensive in recent years.) We can then calculate a Gini coefficient for the citations before and after 1995. (We usually do Gini coefficients for things like income or wealth, but the same idea can be used for citations; think of each cite to an article as a bit of wealth that article gets.) The numbers ended up being: For citations before...

tar.weatherson.org Whois

Domain Name: weatherson.org Registry Domain ID: 8ee8ea794b7b4a17a836e52b21b162a1-LROR Registrar WHOIS Server: whois.networksolutions.com Registrar URL: http://www.networksolutions.com Updated Date: 2022-03-22T13:43:19Z Creation Date: 2006-06-20T14:55:13Z Registry Expiry Date: 2027-06-20T14:55:13Z Registrar: Network Solutions, LLC Registrar IANA ID: 2 Registrar Abuse Contact Email: domain.operations@web.com Registrar Abuse Contact Phone: +1.8777228662 Domain Status: clientTransferProhibited https://icann.org/epp#clientTransferProhibited Registrant State/Province: MI Registrant Country: US Name Server: ns1.totalchoicehosting.com Name Server: ns2.totalchoicehosting.com DNSSEC: unsigned >>> Last update of WHOIS database: 2024-05-17T21:23:46Z <<<